Originally published on
CounterPunch
Killed
at noon, just down the road from the grave of the slave Dred Scott,
Michael Brown has now joined a perennially growing group of dead men and
women (a group that only recently added Trayvon Martin, Oscar Grant,
Eric Garner, Ezell Ford, Renisha McBride, and others) killed by a
combination of institutional racism and systemic poverty. Poverty and
race, of course (like race and wealth), cannot be easily disentangled.
Not only has the man-made construct of race been used to justify
seizures of material resources (gold, timber, land, etc.) from various
locales throughout the world, impoverishing these; it has also justified
enslaving people, creating immense wealth from slave labor. That is,
racial discrimination is not only intertwined with poverty; its obverse,
racial privilege, is a key component of affluence. As such, rather than
the existence of the two Americas we hear so much about (black and
white, rich and poor) there is really mainly one: the parasitic embrace
of its constituent parts.
This entanglement of race and poverty, and the relations of
domination it implies, demonstrates that poverty should also be
regarded as something beyond the absence of economic power. For poverty
refers to a condition in which political power, in addition to economic
power, is absent. In other words, poverty refers to a lack - or, more
accurately, a deprivation - of political-economic power that amounts to
something more than political-economic weakness; it amounts to a
weakness that leaves people vulnerable to such a degree as to constitute
an injury in its own right - a vulnerability which tends to go unseen,
taken for granted, and not easily distinguished from the more
quantitative harms characteristic of poverty, such as high rates of
incarceration, and epidemic levels of preventable diseases.
It is
no coincidence, then, that the term injury is not just etymologically
related but conceptually related to the notion of justice. And justice,
if it means anything at all, requires that this ongoing injury (of
marginalization, exclusion, and abuse) be repaired. But how is a society
to repair such an injury? What type of repairs, or reparations, must be
accomplished to correct this entrenched injustice?
The concept of reparations, of
course, requires some clarification. Just what is it that we mean when
we refer to reparations? In certain respects this concept overlaps with
the equitable notion of restitution - according to which, if justice is
to be effectuated, a party injured or harmed by another must be made
whole - repaired - by the injurer. As this applies to the African
American community, there is no question that the African American
community has been monumentally harmed by the political and economic
institutions of the United States of America. From insurance companies
(such as
Aetna)
who profited enormously from slavery, to industrial and agricultural
companies, not to mention banks, finance, and real estate interests,
tremendous fortunes were made - and continue to be enjoyed - from the
abuse and exploitation of millions of people. The law has a name for
this type of enrichment: unjust enrichment.
Based on the ancient Roman legal maxim nemo locupletari potest aliena iactura - that
none should be enriched from an other's loss - the doctrine of unjust
enrichment holds that when one is enriched at an other's expense,
irrespective of the enriched party's fault, a duty arises to rectify
this by disbursing the unjustly acquired enrichment to those harmed in
its acquisition. According to the doctrine of unjust enrichment, then,
the African American community ought to be reimbursed somehow for the
collective injustice it has suffered. Moreover, those who profited from
this suffering (and continue to enjoy the wealth and privilege derived
from such suffering - a privilege that is nothing short of the obverse
of discrimination) should be dispossessed of this unjustly attained
advantage.
While the African American community may be among the
most wronged people in the history of the US, however, we must not
neglect to note that it does not occupy this category singly. Just as
Ferguson is a suburb of St. Louis, the so-called Gateway to the West,
this gateway opened on to nothing short of the conquest of the continent
- and its appropriation, contrary to legally binding treaties, from
millions of native people. As such, according to the doctrine of unjust
enrichment, the fortunes derived from exploiting the continent ought to
also somehow be removed from those unjustly enriched by this, and
returned to those unjustly deprived.
In spite of the fact that African Americans and indigenous
people have suffered inordinately, it deserves to be mentioned that
women and immigrants from across the world - Ireland, Eastern, Central,
and Southern Europe, China, Vietnam, and the rest of Asia, as well as
from Latin America, among other places - have suffered generations of
exploitation as well. In fields, in the depths of coal mines, and in
countless sweatshops and factories, countless people have been compelled
- at the expense of limbs, lives, and well-being - to produce
tremendous wealth and power for a small class of people.
Consequently, when discussing the issue of reparations and social
justice, we must address the fact that - according to the doctrine of
unjust enrichment, at least - most people in this society - the urban
poor, the rural poor, the working class, and even the middle class -
deserve some form of reparation. How, however, does one begin to repair
this widespread impoverishment?
Because money derives its value in part from scarcity,
exploitation, and debt - and, so, requires poverty and exploitation to
function - money can only superficially correct the basic problem of
poverty/social injustice. Instead of thinking about reparations as the
distribution or redistribution of money, or of other commodities (the
value of which is restricted to its exchange-value - i.e., money), then,
we should recognize that actual justice, and actual peace, requires
social relations that are not regulated by the drive for profit (i.e.,
peace requires social relations that are non-exploitative). As such, a
step toward an actually just society can be accomplished not by
distributing commodities but, rather, by decommodifying that which is
necessary for an actually democratic society. Instead of remaining
within the sphere of commerce, and subject to its whims, that which is
necessary for human flourishing should not be available conditionally,
in exchange for something else. Housing, nutritious food, water (as the
situation in Detroit is making so clear), not to mention health care,
education, communications, transportation, and other resources necessary
for the realization of an actually just,
actually democratic society should
not only be inalienable (not for sale), an actually just society's
priority would be to supply these conditions directly. Producing and
maintaining housing, food, livable cities, healthy ecosystems, and other
conditions, would be a just society's job - as well as its reward.
Beyond the obvious calls for the
demilitarization of the police, and of the removal of money from
politics - and even beyond the more intrepid calls for the abolition of
the United States' metastasizing prison system - actual justice and
actual peace (the absence of which has been amply illustrated by the
unrest in Ferguson) requires not just redistributing political-economic
power; actual justice and actual peace requires neutralizing coercive
political-economic social relations. Beyond the superficial justice
involved in hauling off cops to prison, by de-commodifying and
universally supplying those conditions that are an actually democratic
society's precondition we can move concretely toward social conditions
of actual justice, and actual peace.